The African Ethic of Ubuntu

Author: Thaddeus Metz
Categories: Ethics, Social and Political Philosophy, African Philosophy
Word Count: 998

Listen here

The word “ubuntu” is from some southern African languages and it literally means “humanness.” To have ubuntu is to be a person who is living a genuinely human way of life, whereas to lack ubuntu is to be missing human excellence.

Black people indigenous to Africa commonly believe that one’s basic aim in life should be to exhibit ubuntu, which is done by prizing communal relationships with other people.

This essay reviews this concept and how it informs both the good life and how to act morally.

1. Ubuntu as Cultivating One’s Humanity

Desmond Tutu, South Africa’s renowned Nobel Peace Prize winner, remarks, “When we want to give high praise to someone, we say Yu u nobuntu; Hey, so-and-so has ubuntu.”[1] For many black African cultures, the more one displays ubuntu, that is, develops human excellence, the better one’s life.

This conception of the good life distinguishes two possible ways of living, an animal life and a human one, and claims that one ought to live a genuinely human way of life and avoid living in the manner of a beast or subhuman.

Mogobe Ramose, who has developed a philosophy on ubuntu, says, “One is enjoined, yes, commanded as it were, to actually become a human being.”[2] If someone fails to do so, then many Africans would say of him, “He is not a person” or even “He is an animal.”[3] They would be claiming that, although we are biologically human beings, someone who does not live well has failed to develop the valuable aspects of their human nature.[4]

A self-realization ethic of this sort differs from other conceptions of the good life, particularly those popular among contemporary Western psychologists and philosophers. Most strikingly, this ethic does not focus on hedonic considerations, such as an individual’s pleasure or satisfaction, features that humans share with animals.

2. Ubuntu and Communal Relationship

Many black African societies sum up one’s proper basic aim in life with phrases such as “A person is a person through other persons” or “I am because we are.”[5] These maxims include prescriptive or normative meanings: they instruct one to become a real person or to realize one’s true self, and to do so by relating to other people in certain ways.

More specifically, sub-Saharan conceptions of the good life characteristically understand self-realization in terms of communal or harmonious relationships. Augustine Shutte, one of the first moral philosophers to seriously engage with ubuntu, says:

Our deepest moral obligation is to become more fully human. And this means entering more and more deeply into community with others. So although the goal is personal fulfilment, selfishness is excluded.[6]

So an ubuntu ethic focuses on self-realization, but is also communitarian in nature. This community (or harmony) is an ideal form of interaction between people, a type of relating that people ought to strive to create and to maintain.

Community, or communal relationship, is usefully analyzed as the combination of two interactions: identifying with others and exhibiting solidarity with them.[7]

To identify with others is for people to treat themselves as members of the same group: to conceive of themselves as a “we,” to take pride or feel shame in others’ activities, and to engage in joint projects, coordinating to achieve shared or at least compatible ends.

Solidarity, in part, involves engaging in helpful behavior, acting in ways that are reasonably expected to benefit others. Solidarity involves attitudes, emotions and motives being positively oriented toward others’ good, say, by sympathizing and helping them for their sake.

To see some of the appeal of grounding self-realization on prizing such a communal conception of interaction with others, consider that the union of identifying with others and exhibiting solidarity with them is basically what English speakers mean by a broad sense of “friendship” (or even “love”). Speaking of an African perspective on ethics, Tutu remarks, “Harmony, friendliness, community are great goods.”[8]

There are similarities between a conception of the good life grounded on ideals of ubuntu and Western notions of eudaimonia and virtue. For Aristotle, there is a significant self-regarding element to self-realization, such as theoretical contemplation or self-control, that does not essentially involve other persons (although it often might in practice). In contrast, according to many salient sub-Saharan worldviews, one is to realize oneself solely through others. Realizing oneself is exhausted by exhibiting other-regard, an approach that is attractive at least insofar as we are considering the moral virtues.[9]

3. Ubuntu and Action

Concretely, what is involved in realizing oneself through communal or harmonious relationships with others?

The sub-Saharan tradition characteristically answers this question by appealing to a variety of virtues.[10] One exhibits excellence insofar as one displays character traits such as politeness, kindness, sympathy, compassion, benevolence, altruism, sacrifice, forgiveness, mercy, and tolerance.

It might be thought that realizing oneself by prizing friendliness in these ways demands pacifism, but that is probably not true. By acting in unfriendly or conflicting ways when necessary (and likely) to prevent crime, which involves disrespect and harm, one arguably prizes friendliness and community.

This conception of the good life is meant to guide individuals in the choices they make, and it has also influenced societal decision-making in African societies. Contemporary African intellectuals and policy makers often appeal to ubuntu when thinking about how to organize public and other large-scale institutions.[11] These organizations ought to improve people’s lives, and so they should be structured in ways that foster ubuntu, a plausible view of how best to live.[12]

4. Conclusion

Ubuntu as an ethical perspective and way of life has been in existence for several hundred years among sub-Saharan peoples, even if written scholarship on the topic is new. Ideals associated with ubuntu are one major source of such inspiration, and not merely to those living below the Sahara desert, since its values should be of interest to global readers.

Is the quality of human life enhanced merely by people feeling good, as per a typical contemporary Western approach, or is it better promoted by people exhibiting virtues that are ways of being a friendly person?[13]

Notes

[1] Tutu, 1999, 31

[2] Ramose, 1999, 52.

[3] Bhengu, 1996, 27.

[4] Mnyaka & Motlhabi, 2005, 224–226, 236.

[5] E.g., Mandela, 2013, 227; Mkhize, 2008, 40; Mnyaka & Motlhabi, 2005, 218; Tutu, 1999, 35.

[6] Shutte, 2001, 30; see also Mnyaka & Motlhabi, 2005, 221–228; Tutu, 1999, 35.

[7] These definitional remarks borrow from Metz, 2011, 537–540. Communal or harmonious relationship with others that confer ubuntu on a person is understood as the combination of identity and solidarity. As one South African intellectual, Nkondo, 2007, 91, remarks, “If you asked ubuntu advocates: What principles inform and organise your life?….the answers would express commitment to the good of the community in which their identities were formed, and a need to experience their lives as part of their community.”

[8] Tutu, 1999, 35.

[9] See Metz & Gaie, 2010, 275; Mnyaka & Motlhabi, 2005, 222–228.

[10] See, e.g., Gyekye, 2010; Mnyaka & Motlhabi, 2005; Paris, 1995, 129–156.

[11] See, e.g., Eze, 2010; Murove, 2009; Nkondo, 2007.

[12] Consider two examples from a South African context. First, an ubuntu ethic was largely responsible for the formation of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission that famously dealt with apartheid-era crimes in a non-retributive manner (Tutu, 1999). Second, South Africa’s Constitutional Court appealed to the value of ubuntu in order to judge the death penalty to be inconsistent with the right to life and value of human dignity represented in its Bill of Rights (Cornell & Muvangua, 2011, 65–94).

[13] This essay has been adapted and reprinted with permission from Springer Nature: Metz T. (2014) Ubuntu: The Good Life. In: Michalos A.C. (ed.) Encyclopedia of Quality of Life and Well-Being Research. Springer, Dordrecht. The Editors thank Professor Metz for making this edited and abridged version of his essay available for readers of 1000-Word Philosophy.

References

Bhengu, M. J. (1996). Ubuntu: The essence of democracy. Cape Town, South Africa: Novalis Press.

Cornell, D., & Muvangua, N. (Eds.). (2011). Ubuntu and the law: African ideals and postapartheid jurisprudence. New York: Fordham University Press.

Eze, M. O. (2010). Intellectual history in contemporary South Africa. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Gyekye, K. (2010). “African ethics.” In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy.

Mandela, N. (2013). Nelson Mandela by himself: The authorised book of quotations, S. Hatang and S. Venter, (Eds). Johannesburg, South Africa: Pan Macmillan.

Metz, T. (2011). Ubuntu as a moral theory and human rights in South Africa. African Human Rights Law Journal, 11, 532–559.

Metz, T., & Gaie, J. (2010). The African ethic of ubuntu/ botho: Implications for research on morality. Journal of Moral Education, 39, 273–290.

Mkhize, N. (2008). Ubuntu and harmony: An African approach to morality and ethics. In R. Nicolson (Ed.), Persons in community: African ethics in a global culture (pp. 35–44). Pietermaritzburg, South Africa: University of KwaZulu-Natal Press.

Mnyaka, M., & Motlhabi, M. (2005). The African concept of ubuntu/botho and its socio-moral significance. Black Theology, 3, 215–237.

Murove, M. F. (Ed.). (2009). African ethics: An anthology of comparative and applied ethics. Pietermaritzburg, South Africa: University of KwaZulu-Natal Press.

Nkondo, G. M. (2007). Ubuntu as a public policy in South Africa: A conceptual framework. International Journal of African Renaissance Studies, 2, 88–100.

Paris, P. (1995). The spirituality of African peoples. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.

Ramose, M. (1999). African philosophy through ubuntu. Harare, Zimbabwe: Mond Books.

Shutte, A. (2001). Ubuntu: An ethic for the new South Africa. Cape Town, South Africa: Cluster Publications.

Tutu, D. (1999). No future without forgiveness. New York: Random House.

For Further Reading

Gaie, J. (2007). The Setswana concept of botho: Unpacking the metaphysical and moral aspects. In J. Gaie and S. Mmolai (Eds), The concept of botho and HIV/AIDS in Botswana. Eldoret, Kenya: Zapf Chancery, pp. 29-43.

Khoza, R. (1994). Ubuntu, botho, vumunhu, vhuthu, African humanism. Sandton: Ekhaya Promotions.

Metz, T. (2007). Toward an African moral theory. Journal of Political Philosophy, 15, 321-341.

Mokgoro, Y. (1998). Ubuntu and the law in South Africa. Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal, 1, 15-26.

Murove, M. F. (2016). African moral consciousness. London: Austin Macauley Publishers Ltd.

Related Essays

Virtue Ethics by David Merry

Ethical Egoism by Nathan Nobis

Deontology: Kantian Ethics by Andrew Chapman

Consequentialism by Shane Gronholz

Translation

Turkish

PDF Download

Download this essay in PDF

About the Author

Thaddeus Metz is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Pretoria, South Africa. Professor Metz has published about 250 scholarly papers in value theory and in moral, political and legal philosophy, about half of which address African philosophy. www.up.ac.za/philosophy/article/2923571/preview?module=cms&slug=content-item&id=2923571

Follow 1000-Word Philosophy on Facebook and Twitter and subscribe to receive email notifications of new essays at 1000WordPhilosophy.com