Because God Says So: On Divine Command Theory

Author: Spencer Case
Category: Ethics, Philosophy of Religion
Word Count: 1000

Assuming God exists, what is the relationship between God’s commands and morality? Assuming that God is morally perfect and so commands all and only good things, we may distinguish between two claims:

a. God commands what He does because it is good.

b. What is good is so because of God’s commands.

If (a) is true, then facts about goodness exist independently of God’s will. God’s commands are a response to them. If (b) is true, God’s commands themselves create all truths about goodness and badness.

The philosophical fork in the road between (a) and (b) is known as the “Euthyphro Dilemma,” since a version of it appears in Plato’s dialogue the Euthyphro. To accept (b) is to accept the Divine Command Theory about ethics (henceforth DCT), which shall be our focus here.

1. What Is Divine Command Theory?

Before we continue, let’s first get clear about what DCT isn’t.

DCT isn’t a theory about which particular actions are wrong and right, since it makes no claims about what God in fact commands.

It also isn’t a theory of how we come to know ethical truths. It is silent on how God makes His commandments known, or even whether He chooses to make them known.

Finally, DCT isn’t inconsistent with atheism. The two are logically compatible, but together entail that there are no truths about morality, just as there would be no truths about what’s legal in a state of anarchy.

We should also take care to distinguish DCT from Natural Law Theory (henceforth NLT).

According to NLT, moral facts are grounded in the natural order of the universe and in the natures of human beings. Of course, theists who endorse NLT hold that God created that very natural order, thereby creating the moral order, but this position still differs from DCT. Both theories agree that God created a moral order to the universe, but one holds that God created the moral order through his creation of the natural order, while the other maintains he created the moral order by commanding and forbidding things.

Another way to look at the differences between NLT and DCT is this: If a defender of NLT decided that atheism was, after all, true, he need not abandon his moral theory in order to retain at least some of his moral beliefs. It is at least conceivable that an uncreated natural order grounds ethical truths. However, if a divine command theorist adopted atheism, then he would either have to change his moral theory or conclude that there are no moral truths.

2. Two Worries for Divine Command Theory

While DCT is often appealed to in popular defenses of religion, it’s controversial among religious thinkers. In Christianity, William of Ockham defended DCT, and so did many Protestants, but NLT is a much more common view among Christian philosophers. In Islam, the ‘Asharite school of theology appeared to accept DCT, but the Mu’tazilite school rejected it. Even the views of most ‘Asharites include important qualifications (al-Attar 99-140).

Why do so few really thoughtful believers accept DCT?

Well, think about asking why God prohibits theft, lying, and adultery. We want to say: “Because these things are bad.”

But to give such a justification is to abandon DCT. Per the DCT, that God wills so is supposed to be the explanatory foundation of morality. So, DCT makes God’s commands totally arbitrary.

While one troubling consequence of DCT is arbitrariness, another is the possibility of God’s commanding really horrible things. Think of the morally worst thing conceivable. Whatever you’ve just thought of, if DCT is true, then God could make that thing morally right by commanding it. Wes Morriston formalizes this thought into the following argument against DCT:

  1. DCT entails that whatever God commands is morally obligatory.
  2. God could command X.
  3. So if DCT is true, X could be morally obligatory.
  4. But X could not be morally obligatory.
  5. Therefore, DCT is false. (Morriston 251)

DCT entails (1) and (3), so the defender of DCT must reject at least one of either (2) or (4). One could deny (2) by appealing to God’s eternal and unchanging nature. Perhaps Robert M. Adams could be interpreted as rejecting (2). He endorses a modified version of DCT, according to which the commands must issue from a loving God (Adams 249-276; Morriston 254-259). So maybe God is constrained by his own loving nature. The problem surrounding the rejection of (2) is that it arguably undermines God’s omnipotence.

Rejecting (4) is a kind of response philosophers call “biting the bullet,” since most people who think about the possibility of X’s being morally obligatory have a visceral intuition against it. Among Christian thinkers, William of Ockham comes close to biting that bullet, but even he seems to have wavered (King 239-240). Among Muslim philosophers, Al-‘Ashari stands out as the best example of a thoroughgoing bullet-biter (al-Attar 111-122).

Are there any good arguments for DCT? Perhaps the best way to argue for DCT is to try to show that if you believe in God, then you should accept DCT as the correct moral theory. An appeal to God’s power might be effective here:

  1. God is the most powerful thing conceivable.
  2. Something that can make things right or wrong by will is more powerful than something that can’t.
  3. So, if God can’t make things right or wrong by will then God is not the most powerful thing conceivable (since we can conceive of something that can).
  4. But this is absurd.
  5. Hence, God can make things right or wrong by will (definition of DCT).

This argument alone won’t convince atheists of DCT, since it only works if you assume God exists. However, it could be employed in tandem with other arguments for God’s existence (maybe one of Aquinas’s five arguments, for instance).

Critics of DCT might reject (1) on the grounds that God, as they understand Him, isn’t the most powerful being conceivable FULL STOP, but the most powerful being conceivable who is consistent with all divine attributes, including goodness. Most who have thought deeply on the matter would rather make concessions on omnipotence than accept a morally arbitrary God. Might, it is thought, doesn’t make right. Not even God’s might.

References

Adams, Robert Merrihew. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford University Press. (1999).

al-Attar, Mariam. Islamic Ethics: Divine Command Theory in Arabo-Islamic Thought. Routledge. New York. (2010).

King, Peter “Ockham’s Ethical Theory.” In The Cambridge Companion to Ockham. Edited by Paul Vincent Spade (1999).

Morriston, Wes. “What If God Commanded Something Terrible? A Worry for Divine-Command Meta-Ethics” Religious Studies 45, 249-267. Cambridge University Press (2009).

Plato. Euthyphro. Translated by G.M.A Grube. In Complete Works. Edited with introduction and notes by John M. Cooper. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. (1997).

Related Essays

Attributes of God by Bailie Peterson

G. E. M. Anscombe’s “Modern Moral Philosophy” by Daniel Weltman

Possibility and Necessity: An Introduction to Modality by Andre Leo Rusavuk

Introduction to Deontology: Kantian Ethics by Andrew Chapman

Introduction to Consequentialism by Shane Gronholz

Virtue Ethics by David Merry

Cultural Relativism: Do Cultural Norms Make Actions Right and Wrong? by Nathan Nobis

About the Author

Spencer Case has a Ph.D. in philosophy from the University of Colorado at Boulder. Previously, he served as a public affairs specialist for the U.S. Army in both the Iraq and Afghanistan wars. He also spent nine months in Egypt as a Fulbright Student Grant recipient to study Islamic philosophy. His main interests are ethics, meta-ethics, and comparative philosophy. http://colorado.academia.edu/SpencerCase 

Follow 1000-Word Philosophy on Facebook, Twitter and subscribe to receive email notice of new essays at the bottom of 1000WordPhilosophy.com